IDENTITY POLITICS: ASSESSING THE AMAP (AMO) ROLE
IN PLATEAU STATE OF NIGERIA.
PREAMBLE:
AMO, who call themselves AMAP, are full
time political contributors in the young and nascent
Nigeria’s democracy. Are they identified as Nigerians or
AMAP or both? Are their political manifesto reflecting
national interest, race, clan, ethnicity, community, ward,
chiefdom, Local Government Area, States and the Federal
Capital (the Thirty Six(36) States and Abuja), geo-political
zone (south-south, south east, south west, north east, north
west, north central), region (northern or
southern).Political stalwarts in AMO land have always played
their roles. Great families like THE NABASU FAMILY, THE
MALLUM’S, THE SAMBO’S (THE ROYAL FAMILY), THE KATURA’S, THE
KANDAJI’S, THE AGAG’S , THE UNYA’S, THE KINYANI’S, THE
DABIRAU’S, THE ADANA’S, THE UDAS’, THE SHIGINI’S, THE
KUKULONG’S, THE ZAKIRI’S, THE BINDA’S, THE TAUTAU’S, THE
AGONCHI’S, THE MBUTU’S,THE DULAI’S, THE NUNKUNA’S, THE
BIZINTI’S, THE MADE’S, THE TIMBAU’S, THE KUMUSU’S, THE
BANGAMS, THE TIPINGPINGS, THE KACHOTO’S, THE MACHU’S, THE
KIWA’S, THE MADUGU’S, THE APESE’S, THE MATO’S, THE OBIDA’S,
THE DAMISA’S, and several other prominent
and great families that actively participated in one way or
the other during the nationalist movement before
independence, struggle for independence, and even after
independence to-date (Pre, during, and post independence
era). What type of politics did they play? Were they
nationally inclined? What were their national contributions
to their father land? Till date, what has AMO LAND
benefitted from the Government of the day? At what level are
we playing our politics? Is the impact of Government felt by
our people? If yes, where, how, when? If no, why, when? Is
the level of appointments reflecting the way we are playing
our politics or we are naturally made to be lucky or not as
the case may be? If you go to AMO LAND, will you feel the
presence of Government in the areas of projects, standard of
living, and social amenities? The AMO HERITAGE SIGHTS
located in different areas of the LAND (THE AMO CAVE, THE
IZARA CEREMONY STAGED EVERY AFTER SEVEN YEARS, THE SAMBO
SHADOW, THE AMO MASQUERADES, THE FICHIZA, THE KAPUNGPUNG,
THE IKARBU TRACES, THE IKAURA SERENE ENVIRONMENT, THE
MARVELLOUS MOUNTAINS OF AMO LAND), are they well harnessed?
Again, to what extent has the LAND made the awareness about
the said HERITAGE SIGHTS? The AMO LAND which
is categorized in this way: KIDES, KAZURI and KITARA. KITARA
is subdivided into KITANKALI, LWALANG, and KAMARE. Each
category consists of STRONG PLAYERS, HEROS, POLITICAL
BIGWIGS, STALWARTS, NATIONALISTS, AND OTHERS. [‘Where is he
from’ is dominating the political landscape more than ‘what
can he deliver’?]. Was there any moment
in history that AMO MAN was more responsive to its
obligation? Now is the time for credible, accountable and
sincere representation. We dreamt of it for decades, even
those that conceived it, some did not live to witness its
transformational agenda in the LAND. What else do we have to
say?
INTRODUCTION:
Identity politics are
political arguments that focus upon the
self interest and perspectives of
self-identified social
interest groups and ways in which people's
politics may be shaped by aspects of their identity through
race, class, religion, sexual orientation or traditional
dominance. Not all members of any given group are
necessarily involved in identity politics. Again, the laden
phrase “identity politics” has come to signify a wide range
of political activity and theorizing founded in the shared
experiences of injustice of members of certain social
groups. Rather than organizing solely around belief systems,
programmatic manifestoes, or party affiliation, identity
political formations typically aim to secure the political
freedom of a specific constituency marginalized within its
larger context. Members of that constituency assert or
reclaim ways of understanding their distinctiveness that
challenge dominant oppressive characterizations, with the
goal of greater self-determination. We’re looking at the
motives, methods, and considerations of the political big
wigs spanning through time.
Minority influence is a central component
of identity politics. Minority influence is a form of
social influence which takes place when a
majority is being influenced to accept the
beliefs or
behavior of a minority. Unlike
other forms of influence, this usually involves a personal
shift in private
opinion. This personal shift
in opinion is called conversion. This type of influence is
most likely to take place if the minority is consistent,
flexible and appealing to the majority. AMO is minority
tribe in NIGERIA even though is larger than some ethnic
groups in the Federation Republic of Nigeria. THIS
SMALL-BUT-MIGHTY AMO PEOPLE are politically powerful,
religiously strong, economically viable and socially
civilized.
In discussing this topic, the following
are taken into consideration:
-
1. History and Scope
-
2. Philosophy and Identity
-
3. Liberalism and Identity Politics
-
4. Gender and Feminism
-
5. Race, Ethnicity, and Multiculturalism
-
6. Other Challenges to Identity Politics
-
7. Identity Politics in the 21st
Century
- 8.Homogeneity
and essentialism
- 9. Shared
identity
-
10. Conclusion
-
Bibliography
1. History and Scope
The second half of the twentieth century
saw the emergence of large-scale political movements —
second wave feminism, Black Civil Rights in the U.S., gay
and lesbian liberation, and the American Indian movements,
for example — based in claims about the injustices done to
particular social groups. These social movements are
undergirded by and foster a philosophical body of literature
that takes up questions about the nature, origin and futures
of the identities being defended. Identity politics as a
mode of organizing is intimately connected to the idea that
some social groups are oppressed; that is, that one's
identity as a woman or as a Native American, for example,
makes one peculiarly vulnerable to cultural imperialism
(including stereotyping, erasure, or appropriation of one's
group identity), violence, exploitation, marginalization, or
powerlessness (Young 1990). Identity politics starts from
analyses of oppression to recommend, variously, the
reclaiming, redescription, or transformation of previously
stigmatized accounts of group membership. Rather than
accepting the negative scripts offered by a dominant culture
about one's own inferiority, one transforms one's own sense
of self and community, often through consciousness-raising.
For example, in their germinal statement of Black feminist
identity politics, the Combahee River Collective argued that
“as children we realized that we were different from boys
and that we were treated different — for example, when we
were told in the same breath to be quiet both for the sake
of being ‘ladylike’ and to make us less objectionable in the
eyes of white people. In the process of
consciousness-raising, actually life-sharing, we began to
recognize the commonality of our experiences and, from the
sharing and growing consciousness, to build a politics that
will change our lives and inevitably end our oppression”
(Combahee River Collective 1982, 14-15).
The scope of political movements that may
be described as identity politics is broad: the examples
used in the philosophical literature are predominantly of
struggles within western capitalist democracies, but
indigenous rights movements worldwide, nationalist projects,
or demands for regional self-determination use similar
arguments. Predictably, there is no straightforward
criterion that makes a political struggle into an example of
“identity politics;” rather, the term signifies a loose
collection of political projects, each undertaken by
representatives of a collective with a distinctively
different social location that has hitherto been neglected,
erased, or suppressed. It is beyond the scope of this essay
to offer historical or sociological surveys of the many
different social movements that might be described as
identity politics, although some references to this
literature are provided in the bibliography; instead the
focus here is to provide an overview of the philosophical
issues in the expansive literature in political theory.
The phrase “identity politics” is also
something of a philosophical punching-bag for a variety of
critics. Often challenges fail to make sufficiently clear
their object of critique, using “identity politics” as a
blanket description that invokes a range of tacit political
failings (as discussed in Bickford 1997). From a
contemporary perspective, some early identity claims by
political activists certainly seem naive, totalizing, or
unnuanced. However, the public rhetoric of identity politics
served useful and empowering purposes for some, even while
it sometimes belied the philosophical complexity of any
claim to a shared experience or common group
characteristics. Since the twentieth century heyday of the
well known political movements that made identity politics
so visible, a vast academic literature has sprung up;
although “identity politics” can draw on intellectual
precursors from Mary Wollstonecraft to Frantz Fanon, writing
that actually uses this specific phrase, with all its
contemporary baggage, is limited almost exclusively to the
last twenty years. Thus it was barely as intellectuals
started to systematically outline and defend the
philosophical underpinnings of identity politics that we
simultaneously began to challenge them. At this historical
juncture, then, asking whether one is for or against
identity politics is to ask an impossible question. Wherever
they line up in the debates, thinkers agree that the notion
of identity has become indispensable to
contemporary political discourse, at the same time as they
concur that it has troubling implications for models of the
self, political inclusiveness, and our possibilities for
solidarity and resistance.
2. Philosophy and Identity
From this brief examination of how
identity politics fits into the political landscape it is
already clear that the use of the controversial term
“identity” raises a host of philosophical questions. Logical
uses aside, it is likely familiar to philosophers from the
literature in metaphysics on personal identity — one's sense
of self and its persistence. Indeed, underlying many of the
more overtly pragmatic debates about the merits of identity
politics are philosophical questions about the nature of
subjectivity and the self (Taylor 1989). Charles Taylor
argues that the modern identity is characterized by an
emphasis on its inner voice and capacity for
authenticity — that is, the ability to find a way of
being that is somehow true to oneself (Taylor in Gutmann,
ed. 1994). While doctrines of equality press the notion that
each human being is capable of deploying his or her
practical reason or moral sense to live an authentic live
qua individual, the politics of difference has appropriated
the language of authenticity to describe ways of living that
are true to the identities of marginalized social groups. As
Sonia Kruks puts it:
What makes identity
politics a significant departure from earlier,
pre-identarian forms of the politics of recognition is its
demand for recognition on the basis of the very grounds on
which recognition has previously been denied: it is qua
women, qua blacks, qua lesbians that
groups demand recognition. The demand is not for inclusion
within the fold of “universal humankind” on the basis of
shared human attributes; nor is it for respect “in spite of”
one's differences. Rather, what is demanded is respect for
oneself as different (2001, 85).
For many proponents of identity politics
this demand for authenticity includes appeals to a time
before oppression, or a culture or way of life damaged by
colonialism, imperialism, or even genocide. Thus, for
example, Taiaiake Alfred, in his defense of a return to
traditional indigenous values, argues that:
Indigenous governance
systems embody distinctive political values, radically
different from those of the mainstream. Western notions of
domination (human and natural) are noticeably absent; in
their place we find harmony, autonomy, and respect. We have
a responsibility to recover, understand, and preserve these
values, not only because they represent a unique
contribution to the history of ideas, but because renewal of
respect for traditional values is the only lasting solution
to the political, economic, and social problems that beset
our people. (Alfred 1999, 5)
What is crucial about the “identity” of
identity politics appears to be the experience of the
subject, especially his or her experience of oppression and
the possibility of a shared and more authentic or
self-determined alternative. Thus identity politics rests on
unifying claims about the meaning of politically laden
experiences to diverse individuals. Sometimes the meaning
attributed to a particular experience will diverge from that
of its subject: thus, for example, the woman who struggles
desperately to be attractive may think that she is simply
trying to be a better person, rather than understanding her
experience as part of the disciplining of female bodies in a
patriarchal culture. Making sense of such disjunctions
relies on notions such as false consciousness — the
systematic mystification of the experience of the oppressed
by the perspective of the dominant. Thus despite the
disagreements of many defenders of identity political claims
with Marxism and other radical political models, they share
the view that individuals' perceptions of their own
interests may be systematically distorted and must be
somehow freed of their misperceptions by group-based
transformation.
Concern about this aspect of identity
politics has crystallized around the transparency of
experience to the oppressed, and the univocality of its
interpretation. Experience is never, critics argue, simply
epistemically available prior to interpretation (Scott
1992); rather it requires a theoretical framework — implicit
or explicit — to give it meaning. Moreover, if experience is
the origin of politics, then some critics worry that what
Kruks (2001) calls “an epistemology of provenance” will
become the norm: on this view, political perspectives gain
legitimacy by virtue of their articulation by subjects of
particular experiences. This, critics charge, closes off the
possibility of critique of these perspectives by those who
don't share the experience, which in turn inhibits political
dialogue and coalition-building.
ü
From these understandings
of subjectivity, it is easy to see how critics of identity
politics, and even some cautious supporters, have feared
that it is prone to essentialism. This expression
is another philosophical term of abuse, intended to capture
a multitude of sins. In its original contexts in
metaphysics, the term implies the belief that an object has
a certain quality by virtue of which it is what it is; for
Locke, famously, the essence of a triangle is that it is a
three-sided shape. In the contemporary humanities the term
is used more loosely to imply, most commonly, an
illegitimate generalization about identity (Heyes 2000). In
the case of identity politics, two claims stand out as
plausibly “essentialist:” the first is the understanding of
the subject that characterizes a single axis of identity as
discrete and taking priority in representing the self--as if
being Asian-American, for example, were entirely separable
from being a woman. To the extent that identity politics
urges mobilization around a single axis, it will put
pressure on participants to identify that axis as their
defining feature, when in fact they may well understand
themselves as integrated selves who cannot be represented so
selectively or even reductively (Spelman 1988). The second
form of essentialism is closely related to the first:
generalizations made about particular social groups in the
context of identity politics may come to have a disciplinary
function within the group, not just describing but also
dictating the self-understanding that its members should
have. Thus, the supposedly liberatory new identity may
inhibit autonomy, as Anthony Appiah puts it, replacing “one
kind of tyranny with another” (Appiah in Gutmann ed. 1994,
163). Just as dominant groups in the culture at large insist
that the marginalized integrate by assimilating to dominant
norms, so within some practices of identity politics
dominant sub-groups may, in theory and practice, impose
their vision of the group's identity onto all its members.
For example, in his films Black Is, Black ain’t and
Tongues Untied Marlon Riggs eloquently portrays the
exclusion of Black women and gay Black men from heterosexist
and masculinist understandings of African-American identity
politics.
Or, theorizing the experience of
hybridity for those whose identities are especially far from
norms of univocality, Gloria Anzaldúa, for example, famously
writes of her mestiza identity as a Chicana,
American, raised poor, a lesbian and a feminist, living in
the metaphoric and literal Borderlands of the American
Southwest (Anzaldúa 1999 [1987]). Some suggest the
deployment of “strategic essentialism:” we should act as
ifan identity was uniform only to achieve interim
political goals, without implying any deeper authenticity
(Spivak 1990, 1-16). Others argue that a relational social
ontology, which makes clear the fluidity and interdependence
of social groups, should be developed as an alternative to
the reification of other approaches to identity politics
(Young 2000; Nelson 2001). These accounts of subjectivity,
ontologies, and ways of understanding solidarity and
relationships are at the forefront of contemporary
philosophical scholarship in identity politics.
3. Liberalism and Identity
Politics
A key condition of possibility for
contemporary identity politics was institutionalized liberal
democracy (Brown 1995). The citizen mobilizations that made
democracy real also shaped and unified groups previously
marginal to the polity, while extensions of formal rights
invited expectations of material and symbolic equality. The
perceived paucity of rewards offered by liberal capitalism,
however, spurred forms of radical critique that sought to
explain the persistence of oppression. At the most basic
philosophical level, critics of liberalism suggested that
liberal social ontology — the model of the nature of and
relationship between subjects and collectives — was
misguided. The social ontology of most liberal political
theories consists of citizens conceptualized as essentially
similar individuals, as for example in John Rawls' famous
thought experiment using the “original position,” in which
representatives of the citizenry are conceptually divested
of all specific identities or affiliations in order to make
rational decisions about the social contract (Rawls 1970).
To the extent that group interests are represented in
liberal polities, they tend to be understood as
associational, forms of interest group pluralism whereby
those sharing particular interests voluntarily join together
to create a political lobby. Citizens are free to register
their individual preferences (through voting, for example),
or to aggregate themselves for the opportunity to lobby more
systematically (e.g. by forming an association such as a
neighborhood community league). These lobbies, however, are
not defined by the identity of their members so much as by
specific shared interests and goals, and when pressing their
case the marginalized subjectivity of the group members is
not itself called into question. Finally, political parties,
the other primary organs of liberal democratic government,
critics suggest, have few moments of inclusivity, being
organized around party discipline, responsiveness to lobby
groups, and broad-based electoral popularity. Ultimately
conventional liberal democracy, diverse radical critics
claim, cannot effectively address the ongoing structural
marginalization that persists in late capitalist liberal
states, and may even be complicit with it (Young 1990; P.
Williams 1991; Brown 1995; M. Williams 1998).
On a philosophical level, these
understandings of the political subject and its relationship
to collectivity came to seem inadequate to ensuring
representation for women, gays and lesbians, or
racial-ethnic groups (M. Williams 1998). Critics charged
that the neutral citizen of liberal theory was in fact the
bearer of an identity coded white, male, bourgeois,
able-bodied, and heterosexual (Pateman 1988; Young 1990; Di
Stefano 1991; Mills 1997). This implicit ontology in part
explained the persistent historical failure of liberal
democracies to achieve anything more than token inclusion in
power structures for members of marginalized groups. A
richer understanding of political subjects as constituted
through and by their social location was required. In
particular, the history and experience of oppression brought
with it certain perspectives and needs that could not be
assimilated through existing liberal structures. Individuals
are oppressed by virtue of their membership in a particular
social group — that is, a collective whose members
have relatively little mobility into or out of the
collective, who usually experience their membership as
involuntary, who are generally identified as members by
others, and whose opportunities are deeply shaped by the
relation of their group to corollary groups through
privilege and oppression. Oppression, then, is the
systematic limiting of opportunity or constraints on
self-determination because of such membership: for example,
Frantz Fanon eloquently describes the experience of being
always constrained by the white gaze as a Black man: “I
already knew that there were legends, stories, history, and
above all historicity… I was responsible at the
same time for my body, my race, and for my ancestors” (Fanon
1968, 112). Conversely, members of dominant groups are
privileged — systematically advantaged by the
deprivations imposed on the oppressed. For example, in a
widely cited article Peggy McIntosh identifies whiteness as
a dominant identity, and lists 47 ways in which she is
advantaged by being white compared with her colleagues of
color. These range from being able to buy “flesh-colored”
Band-Aids that will match her skin tone, to knowing that she
can be rude without provoking negative judgments of her
racial group, to being able to buy a house in a middle-class
community without risking neighbors' disapproval (1993).
Critics have also charged that
assimilation (or, less provocatively, integration) is a
guiding principle of liberalism. If the liberal subject is
coded in the way Young (1990) suggests, then attempts to
apply liberal norms of equality will risk demanding that the
marginalized conform to the identities of their oppressors.
For example, many gays and lesbians have objected to
campaigns to institute “gay marriage” on the grounds that
these legal developments assimilate same-sex relationships
to a heterosexual model, rather than challenging its
historical, material, and symbolic terms. If this is
equality, they claim, and then it looks suspiciously
like the erasure of socially subordinate identities rather
than their genuine incorporation into the polity. This
suspicion helps to explain the affiliation of identity
politics with separatism. This latter is a set of
positions that share the view that attempts at integration
of dominant and marginalized groups so consistently
compromise the identity or potential of the less powerful
that a distinct social and political space is the only
structure that will adequately protect them. In Canada, for
example, Québec separatists claim that the French language
and francophone culture are persistently erased within an
overwhelmingly dominant Anglo-American continent, despite
the efforts of the Canadian state to maintain its official
bilingualism and to integrate Québec into the nation. Given
their long history of conflict and marginalization, a
separate and sovereign Québec, they argue, is the only
plausible solution (e.g. Laforest in Beiner and Norman
2001). Analogous arguments have been made on behalf of
Native American and other indigenous peoples and African
Americans (e.g. Alfred 1999, Asante 2000). Lesbian feminist
separatists have claimed that the central mechanism for the
oppression of women under patriarchy is heterosexuality.
Understanding heterosexuality as a forced contract or
compulsory institution, they argue that women's
relationships with men are persistently characterized by
domination and subordination. Only divorce (literal and
figurative) and the creation of new geographic and political
communities of woman-identified women will end patriarchal
exploitation, and forge a liberatory female identity (Rich
1980; Frye 1983; Radicalesbians 1988; Wittig 1992).
One of the central charges against
identity politics by liberals, among others, has been its
alleged reliance on notions of sameness to justify political
mobilization. Looking for people who are like you
rather than who share your political values as allies runs
the risk of sidelining critical political analysis of
complex social locations and ghettoizing members of social
groups as the only persons capable of making or
understanding claims to justice. After an initial wave of
relatively uncompromising identity politics, proponents have
taken these criticisms to heart and moved to more
philosophically nuanced accounts that appeal to
coalitions as better organizing structures. On this
view, separatism around a single identity formation must be
muted by recognition of the internally heterogeneous and
overlapping nature of social group memberships. The idea of
a dominant identity from which the oppressed may need to
dissociate themselves remains, but the alternative becomes a
more fluid and diverse grouping, less intent on guarantees
of internal homogeneity and more concerned with identifying
“family resemblances” than literal identity (Heyes 2000).
This trajectory — from formal inclusion
in liberal polities, to assertions of difference and new
demands under the rubric of identity politics, to internal
and external critique of identity political movements — has
taken different forms in relation to different identities.
Increasingly it is difficult to see what divides
contemporary positions, and some commentators have suggested
possible rapprochements between liberalism and
identity politics (e.g. Laden 2001). A problem in sorting
through such claims is the vagueness of philosophical
discussions of identity politics, which are often content to
list their rubric under the mantra of “gender, race, class,
etc.” although these three are not obviously analogous, nor
is it clear which identities are gestured toward by the
predictable “etc.” (Or why they do not merit naming). Class
in particular has a distinctively different political
history, and contemporary critics of identity politics, as
I'll discuss below, often take themselves to be defending
class analysis against identity politics' depoliticizing
effects. Of those many forms of identity politics to which
large academic literatures attach, however, I'll briefly
highlight key issues concerning gender, sexuality, and a
complex cluster of race, ethnicity and multiculturalism.
4. Gender and Feminism
Feminism in AMO LAND played a dominant
role in shaping so many things. Twentieth century feminism
has consistently opposed biological determinism: the view
that shared biological features among a certain group lead
inevitably to certain social roles or functions. For
example, one early opponent of women's suffrage suggested
that women and men had different metabolic systems —
katabolic (or “energy-expending”) in men, and anabolic (or
“energy-conserving”) in women — that precluded women's
effective or informed participation in politics (see Moi
2000, 3-21 for discussion). Feminist identity politics,
then, takes up the task of articulating women's
understandings of themselves (and of men) without reducing
femininity (or masculine dominance) to biology. Whatever
experiences women share will be experiences of femininity
not necessarily resulting from an immutable sexual
difference but rather from social injustice. Put less
usefully, perhaps, although sex (the features of bodies we
typically aggregate as male and female) may be biological,
gender (the social roles we call femininity and masculinity)
is “socially constructed.” Claims about the ”social
construction” of the identities of identity politics
permeate the field as a logical extension of its mandate,
although with tremendous philosophical vagueness attaching
to the content of the phrase, which serves primarily to
emphasize the contingency of (the content of) any particular
category or concept (see Haslanger 1995, 2005; Hacking
1999). The fear of biological determinism has led to
tremendous caution in feminist theorizing: any invocation of
features of female bodies as a basis for identity political
claims risks being seen as (inadvertently) complicit with
sexist views. Furthermore, the very idea of reclaiming
women's identities from patriarchy has been criticized as
merely an affirmation of a slave morality — a Nietzschean
term describing the attachments of the oppressed as they
rationalize and valorize their condition. Attempts from
various quarters to capture and revalue the distinctively
feminine (by theorizing, for example,”maternal thinking,”
[Ruddick 1989], or écriture féminine [Irigaray 1985]) risk,
critics claim, endorsing existing power relations. Thus the
heated debates surrounding the”ethic of care” in moral
psychology, for example, line up around two constellations
of positions: on the one hand, advocates of the ethic of
care as a distinctively feminine contribution to moral
reasoning point to its benefits for negotiating a human
social world characterized by webs of relationship, and to
the pathologies of the dissociation that is culturally
linked to masculinities. Carol Gilligan is the best known
proponent of this position (although the details of her
complex paradigm are often glossed over or misrepresented)
(Gilligan 1993 [1982]). Her critics charge that she reifies
femininity — were women not oppressed, they would not speak
in the voice of care, thus casting doubt on the desirability
of attempts to reclaim it as part of a liberatory framework.
In other words, the current construction of femininity is so
deeply imbricated with the oppression of women that such
attempts will always end up reinforcing the very discourse
they seek to undermine (Butler 1999 [1990]); this critique
has strong affiliations with poststructuralism (which are
discussed below).
The narrative of feminist interpretation
of gender relations most commonly offered points to
universalizing claims made on behalf of women during the
so-called “second wave” of the feminist movement in the late
1960's and 1970's in Western countries. The most often
discussed (and criticized) second wave feminist icons —
women such as Betty Friedan or Gloria Steinem — are white,
middle-class, and heterosexual, although this historical
picture too often neglects the contributions of lesbian
feminists, feminists of color, and working-class feminists,
which were less visible in popular culture, perhaps, but
arguably equally influential in the lives of women. For some
early radical feminists, women's oppression as women
was the core of identity politics, and should not be diluted
with other identity issues. For example, Shulamith
Firestone, in her classic book The Dialectic of Sex,
argued that “racism is sexism extended,” and that
the Black Power movement represented only sexist cooptation
of Black women into a new kind of subservience to Black men.
Thus for Black women to fight racism (especially among white
women) was to divide the feminist movement, which properly
focused on challenging patriarchy, understood as struggle
between men and women, the foundational dynamic of all
oppressions (Firestone 1970, esp. 103-120).
Claims about the universality of gender
made during the second wave have been extensively criticized
in feminist theory for failing to recognize the specificity
of their own constituencies. For example, Friedan's famous
proposition that women needed to get out of the household
and into the professional workplace was, bell hooks pointed
out, predicated on the experience of a post-war generation
of white, middle-class married women confined to
housekeeping and child-rearing by their professional
husbands (Friedan 1963; hooks 1981). Many women of color and
working-class women had worked outside their homes
(sometimes in other women's homes) for decades;
some lesbians had a history of working in traditionally male
occupations or living alternative domestic lives without a
man's “family wage.” Similarly, some women from the less
developed world have been critical of Northern feminist
theory for globalizing its claims. Such moves construct
"Third World" women, they argue, as less developed or
enlightened versions of their "First World" counterparts,
rather than understanding their distinctively different
situation (Mohanty 1988); or, they characterize liberation
for Northern women in ways that exacerbate the exploitation
of the global poor: by supporting economic conditions in
which increasing numbers of western women can abuse
immigrant domestic workers, for example (Anderson 2000).
Thus feminist claims made about the
oppression of women founded in a notion of shared experience
and identity is now invariably greeted with philosophical
suspicion. Some critics have charged that this suspicion
itself has become excessive, undercutting the very
possibility of generalizations about women that gives
feminist theory its force (Martin 1994), or that it marks
the distancing of feminist philosophy from its roots in
political organizing. Others suggest alternative methods for
feminist theory that will minimize the emphasis on shared
criteria of membership in a social group and stress instead
the possibilities for alliances founded on non-identical
connections (Young 1997; Heyes 2000; Cornell 2000). It is
commonplace to hear that “identity” is a term in serious
crisis in feminist thought, and that feminist praxis must
move beyond identity politics (Dean 1996). Nonetheless,
sex-gender as a set of analytical categories continues to
guide feminist thought, albeit in troubled and troubling
ways.
5. Race, Ethnicity, and
Multiculturalism
Similar debates in philosophy of race
highlight the contingent and historical nature of “race” as
a category of identity. Despite a complex history of
biological essentialism in the presentation of racial
typologies, the notion of a genetic basis to racial
difference has been largely discredited; the criteria
different societies (at different times) use to organize and
hierarchize “racial formations” are political and contingent
(Omi and Winant 1986). While skin colour, appearance of
facial features, or hair type is in some trivial sense
genetically determined, the grouping of different persons
into races does not pick out any patterned
biological difference. What it does pick out is a set of
social meanings with political ramifications (Alcoff 1997,
2006). The most notorious example of an attempt to
rationalize racial difference as biological is the U.S.
“one-drop rule,” under which an individual was characterized
as Black if they had “one drop” or more of “Black blood.”
Adrian Piper points out that not only does this belief
persist into contemporary readings of racial identity, it
also implies that given the prolonged history of racial
mixing in the US — coerced and voluntary — very significant
numbers of nominally “white” people in the U.S. today should
be re-classified as “Black” (Piper 1996). But the case in
AMO land is that of area (RUNZU, KITARA, AND KIDES), clan
(LIGULA, ASANA, ADAZA, APALI, ACHU, ADOP, LIKI, ASIRNE,
LIKURI, ANAN DIKPOK, AZE, AND A HOST OF OTHERS), and
families as discussed above. In those countries that have
had official racial classifications, individuals' struggles
to be re-classified (almost always as a member of a more
privileged racial group) are often invoked to highlight the
contingency of race, especially at the borders of its
categories. And a number of histories of racial groups that
have apparently changed their racial identification — Jews,
Italians, Yoruba, Igbo, Hausa, Berom, Amo, or the Irish, for
example — also illustrate social constructionist theses
(Ignatiev 1995). The claim that race is “socially
constructed,” however, does not in itself mark out a
specific identity politics. Indeed, the very contingency of
race and its lack of correlation with categories that have
more meaning in everyday life (such as ethnicity or culture)
may circumscribe its political usefulness: just as feminists
have found the limits of appeals to “women's identity,” so
Asian-Americans may find with ethnicities and cultures as
diverse as Chinese, Indian, or Vietnamese that their racial
designation itself provides little common ground. That a US
citizen of both Norwegian and Ashkenazi Jewish heritage will
check that they are “white” on a census form says relatively
little (although nonetheless something) about their
experience of their identity, or indeed of their very
different relationship to anti-Semitism. Tropes of
separatism and the search for forms of authentic
self-expression are related to race via ethno-cultural
understandings of identity: for example, the U.S.
Afro-centric movement appeals to the cultural significance
of African heritage for Black Americans (Asante 2000).
Racial categories are perhaps most
politically significant in their contested relation to
racism. Racism attempts to reduce members of social groups
to their racial features, drawing on a complex history of
racial stereotypes to do so. Racism is arguably analogous to
other forms of oppression in being both overt and
institutionalized, manifested both as deliberate acts by
individuals and as unplanned systemic outcomes. The specific
direction of US discussion of the categories of race has
been around color-blind versus color-conscious public policy
(Appiah and Gutmann 1996). Color-blindness — that is, the
view that race should be ignored in public policy
and everyday exchange — has hegemony in popular discourse.
Drawing attention to race — whether in a personal
description or in university admissions procedures — is
unfair and racist. Advocates of color-consciousness, on the
other hand, argue that racism will not disappear without
proactive efforts, which require the invocation of race.
Thus affirmative action, for example, requires statistics
about the numbers of members of oppressed racial groups
employed in certain contexts, which in turn requires racial
identification and categorization. Thus those working
against racism face a paradox familiar in identity politics:
the very identity they aim to dispel must be invoked to make
their case.
The literature on multiculturalism takes
up questions of race, ethnicity, and cultural diversity in
relation to the liberal state. Some multicultural states —
notably Canada — allegedly aim to permit the various
cultural identities of their residents to be preserved
rather than assimilated, despite the concern that the
over-arching liberal aims of such states may be at odds with
the values of those they claim to protect. For example,
Susan Moller Okin argues that multiculturalism is sometimes
bad for women, especially when it works to preserve
patriarchal values in minority cultures. If multiculturalism
implies a form of cultural relativism that prevents judgment
of or interference with the “private” practices of
minorities, female genital mutilation, forced marriage,
compulsory veiling, or being deprived of education may be
the consequence. Okin's critics counter that she falsely
portrays culture as static, internally homogeneous, and
defined by men's values, allowing liberalism to represent a
culturally unmarked medium for the defense of individual
rights (Okin et al 1999). For many commentators on
multiculturalism this is the nub of the issue: is there an
inconsistency between defending the rights of minority
cultures, while prohibiting those (allegedly) cultural
practices that the state judges illiberal (Eisenberg and
Spinner-Halev 2005; Phillips 2007)? Can liberalism sustain
the cultural and value-neutrality that some commentators
still ascribe to it, or to what extent should it embraces
its own cultural specificity (Taylor, Habermas in Gutmann,
ed. 1994; Lawrence and Herzog, eds. 1994; Kymlicka, ed.
1995; Deveaux 2000)? Defenders of the right to cultural
expression of minorities in multicultural states thus
practice forms of identity politics that are both made
possible by liberalism and sometimes in tension with it (see
Laden and Owen eds. 2007).
6. Other Challenges to
Identity Politics
Since its 1970s vogue, identity politics
as a mode of organizing and set of political philosophical
positions has undergone numerous attacks by those motivated
to point to its flaws, whether by its pragmatic exclusions
or more programmatically as liberals, Marxists, or
poststructuralists. For many leftist commentators, identity
politics is something of a bête noire, representing
the capitulation to cultural criticism in place of analysis
of the material roots of oppression. Marxists, both orthodox
and revisionist, and socialists — especially those who came
of age during the rise of the New Left in western countries
— have often interpreted the perceived ascendancy of
identity politics as representing the end of radical
materialist critique (Farred 2000). Identity politics, for
these critics, is both factionalizing and depoliticizing,
drawing attention away from the ravages of late capitalism
toward super structural cultural accommodations that leave
economic structures unchanged. For example, while allowing
that both recognition and redistribution have a place in
contemporary politics, Nancy Fraser laments the supremacy of
perspectives that take injustice to inhere in “cultural”
constructions of identity that the people to whom they are
attributed want to reject. Such recognition models, she
argues, require remedies that “valorize the group's
‘groupness’ by recognizing its specificity,” thus reifying
identities that themselves are products of oppressive
structures. By contrast, injustices of distribution require
redistributive remedies that aim “to put the group out of
business as a group” (Fraser 1997, 19).
The reasons given for this alleged turn
away from economic oppression to themes of culture,
language, and identity in contemporary politics differ.
First, the institutionalization of North American radicalism
in the middle-class bastion of academia creates incentives
for intellectuals to minimize the political importance of
their own class privilege, and focus instead on other
identities (in turn divorced from their economic
inflections). Second, Wendy Brown suggests that capitalist
suffering has been displaced onto other identities,
interpreted through the lens of class aspiration (Brown
1995, 59-60). Third, the turn away from economic analysis
may be less dramatic than some critics believe: recent
activism against global capitalism indicates resurgence in
economic critique that is now arguably more fully imbricated
with identity politics (Lott 2000). Finally, the rise of
diverse “postmodern” paradigms offers sophisticated
theoretical alternatives to Marxism for those on the left.
Of these, poststructuralist challenges to
identity politics are perhaps the most philosophically
developed and profound. Poststructuralists charge that
identity politics rests on a mistaken view of the subject
that assumes a metaphysics of substance — that is,
that a cohesive, self-identical subject is ontologically (if
not actually) prior to any form of social injustice (Butler
1999). This subject has certain core essential attributes
that define her or his identity, over which are imposed
forms of socialization that cause her or him to internalize
other nonessential attributes. This position, they suggest,
misrepresents both the ontology of identity and its
political significance. The alternative view offered by
poststructuralists is that the subject is itself always
already a product of discourse, which represents both the
condition of possibility for a certain subject-position and
a constraint on what forms of self-making individuals, may
engage. There is no real identity--individual or
group-based--that is separable from its conditions of
possibility, and any political appeal to identity formations
must engage with the paradox of acting from the very
subject-positions it must also oppose. Central to this
position is the observation that any claim to identity must
organize itself around a constitutive exclusion:
An identity is
established in relation to a series of differences that have
become socially recognized. These differences are essential
to its being. If they did not coexist as differences, it
would not exist in its distinctness and solidity. Entrenched
in this indispensable relation is a second set of
tendencies, themselves in need of exploration, to conceal
established identities into fixed forms, thought and lived
as if their structure expressed the true order of things.
When these pressures prevail, the maintenance of one
identity (or field of identities) involves the conversion of
some differences into otherness, into evil, or one of its
numerous surrogates. Identity requires differences in order
to be, and it converts difference into otherness in order to
secure its own self-certainty. (Connolly 2002, 64)
The dangers of identity politics, then,
are that it casts as authentic to the self or group an
identity that in fact is defined by its opposition to
another. Reclaiming such an identity as one's own merely
reinforces its dependence on this dominant other, and
further internalizes and reinforces an oppressive hierarchy.
While the charge that identity politics promotes a victim
mentality is often a facile pot-shot, Wendy Brown offers a
more sophisticated caution against the dangers of
resentment (the moralizing revenge of the powerless).
She argues that identity politics has its own genealogy in
liberal capitalism that relentlessly reinforces the “wounded
attachments” it claims to sever: “Politicized identity thus
enunciates itself, makes claims for itself, only by
entrenching, restating, dramatizing, and inscribing its pain
in politics; it can hold out no future — for itself or
others — that triumphs over this pain” (Brown 1995, 74).
What political alternatives does this
model imply? Proponents of identity politics have suggested
that poststructuralism are politically impotent, capable
only of deconstruction and never of action (Hartsock 1998,
205-226). Yet there are political projects motivated by
poststructuralist theses. For example, Judith Butler's
famous articulation of performativity as a way of
understanding subject-development suggests to her and others
the possibility of disarticulating seamless performances to
subvert the meanings with which they are invested (Butler
1999 [1990]). Drag can constitute such a disarticulation,
although other critics have suggested other examples; Adrian
Piper's conceptual art seeks to disrupt the presumed
self-identity of race by showing how it is actively
interpreted and reconstituted, never determinate and
self-evident.
7. Identity Politics in the
21st Century
The continuing intellectual crisis
surrounding identity politics paradoxically marks its
importance to contemporary political philosophy and
practice. Both flexible and extensible, identity political
tropes continue to influence new political claims: an
extensive literature approaches disability, for example, as
a set of experiences of social injustice that sediment
self-understandings among the disabled and motivate a
politics of disability that refuses the legacy of charity to
insist that the dominant culture change its exclusionary
social practices rather than represent itself as generously
accommodating the “special” demands of the disabled (Wendell
1996; Davis 1997 [2006]; Silvers 1998). On less well
traversed political philosophical ground: can identity
politics be extended to children, for example, as the
emergent children's rights movement implies? Identity
politics has limits, too: is it too person-centered? How can
identity politics also be an environmental politics
(Sandilands 2000)? Perhaps most important for philosophers,
any idea of identity itself appears to be in a period of
rapid evolution. Changing technologies are having a profound
impact on our philosophical understandings of who we are.
Attempts to decode human genetics and possibly shape the
genetic make-up of future persons (Wald 2000), to clone
human beings, or to xeno-transplant animal organs, and so
on, all raise deep philosophical questions about the kind of
thing a person is. We are capable of changing our bodies in
ways that dramatically change our identities, including
through sex change or cosmetic surgeries, with immediate
consequences for the kinds of identities I have been
discussing in this essay. As more and more people form
political alliances using disembodied communications
technologies, the kinds of identities that matter seem also
to shift (Turkle 1995). Behaviors, beliefs, and
self-understandings are increasingly pathologized as
syndromes and disorders, including through the
identification of new “types” of person (in turn generating
possibilities for new forms of identity politics) (Elliott
2003a and 2003b; Rose 1997). At the same time, familiar
mechanisms of oppression are further entrenching the very
identities that may be fragmenting in some western, wealthy
contexts. Global capitalism appears to be widening the gap
between the over- and less-developed countries, and working
to further marginalize women, ethnic or indigenous
minorities, and the disabled in the so-called Third and
Fourth Worlds.[1]
This mass of shifts and contradictions might be thought to
mark the end of the era of identity politics. Whatever
limits are inherent to identity political formations,
however, the unfashionableness of the phrase itself belies
the deep implication of questions of power and legitimate
government with demands for self-determination that are
unlikely to fade away.
8. Homogeneity
and essentialism
Some critics counter that the intolerant
homogeneity of mainstream culture is precisely the fact that
makes full acceptance impossible, and that social justice
movements should aim not toward integration but rather
multicultural pluralism, without recourse to the types of
oppressive homogeneity now at play. (See the work of
Urvashi Vaid for a discussion of the perils
of homogeneity.)
Other critics of identity politics claim
that it tends toward
essentialism, arguing that some of its
proponents assume or imply that gender, race, or other group
characteristics are fixed or biologically determined traits
(or, in the case of gay liberation, based on the
Freudian idea that we're all driven by our
sexuality), rather than social constructions. Such criticism
is most common with regard to groups based on claims of
gender or sexual orientation, where the nature of the
defining trait is in dispute.
9.
Shared
identity
Still other critics have argued that
groups based on shared identity, other than class (e.g.:
religious identity or neurological wiring), can divert
energy and attention from more fundamental issues, such as
class conflict in
capitalist societies. Even those who
support
gay rights, ending
racism or
freedom of religion, for instance, may
consider these side issues at best.
Such arguments have been expressed by a
number of writers, such as
Eric Hobsbawm,[6]
Todd Gitlin,[7]
Michael Tomasky,
Richard Rorty,
Sean Wilentz,
Robert W. McChesney, Bart Landry, and
Jim Sleeper.[8]
Hobsbawm, in particular, has criticized nationalisms, and
the principle of national self-determination adopted
internationally after
World War I, since national governments are
often merely an expression of a ruling class or power, and
their proliferation was a source of the wars of the
twentieth century. Hence Hobsbawm argues that identity
politics, such as
queer nationalism,
Islamism,
Cornish nationalism or
Ulster Loyalism are just other versions of
bourgeois nationalism.
10. CONCLUSION.
So many things have been said about
identity politics with a special interest in the AMO LAND.
Politics has to be played with a national reflection rather
than considering your race, gender, philosophy, tribe,
social status or any other thing. It has to put the interest
of the nation first. Let us look at developed economies or
first world countries like THE US, THE UK, GERMANY, JAPAN,
CHINA, FRANCE, RUSSIA, CANADA, developing economies or
second world countries like BRAZIL, SOUTH AFRICA, under
developed economies or third world countries like MOST
AFRICAN, ASIAN, AND SOUTH AMERICAN COUNTRIES, have all
played politics with national interests rather than
individualistic, tribal, and other selfish considerations.
We have big political names in AMO LAND as mentioned above.
When we strengthen our base, we will be at a better position
to strengthen our nation. But national interest should be
our guiding principle.
Bibliography
·
Alcoff, Linda
Martin. 1997. “Philosophy and Racial Identity.”
Philosophy Today 41:1-4:67-76.
·
–––. 2006. “Visible
Identities: Race, Gender, and the Self.” New
York: Oxford University
Press.
·
Amo historical
archives
·
Alfred, Taiaiake.
1999. Peace, Power, and Righteousness: An Indigenous
Manifesto. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
·
Anderson, Bridget.
2000. Doing the Dirty Work? The Global Politics of
Domestic Labour. London: Zed Books.
·
Anzaldúa, Gloria.
1999 (1987). Borderlands/La Frontera: The New Mestiza.
San Francisco: Aunt Lute.
·
Appiah, Anthony and
Amy Gutmann. 1996. Color Conscious: The Political
Morality of Race. Princeton: Princeton University
Press.
·
Asante, Molefi K.
1998. The Afrocentric Idea. Philadelphia: Temple
University Press.
·
–––. 2000. The
Painful Demise of Eurocentrism: An Afrocentric Response to
Critics. Africa World Press.
·
Bickford, Susan.
1997. “Anti-Anti-Identity Politics: Feminism, Democracy, and
the Complexities of Citizenship.” Hypatia 12:4:
111-31.
·
Blasius, Mark (Ed).
2001. Sexual Identities, Queer Politics. Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
·
Brown, Wendy. 1995.
States of Injury: Power and Freedom in Late Modernity.
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
·
Butler, Judith. 1999
[1990]. Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of
Identity. New York: Routledge.
·
The Combahee River
Collective. 1982. “A Black Feminist Statement,” in All
the Women are White, All the Blacks are Men, But Some of Us
Are Brave: Black Women's Studies, Gloria T. Hull,
Patricia Bell Scott, and Barbara Smith (eds). New York:
Feminist Press.
·
Connolly, William.
2002. Identity\Difference: Democratic
Negotiations of Political Paradox. Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press.
·
Cornell, Drucilla.
2000. Just Cause: Freedom, Identity, and Rights.
Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
·
Davis, Lennard J.
(Ed.). 2006 [1997]. The Disability Studies Reader.
New York: Routledge.
·
Dean, Jodi. 1996.
Solidarity of Strangers: Feminism after Identity
Politics. Berkeley: University of California Press.
·
Deveax, Monique.
2000. Cultural Pluralism and Dilemmas of Justice
Ithaca, Cornell University Press.
·
Di Stefano,
Christine. 1991. Configurations of Masculinity: A
Feminist Perspective on Modern Political Theory.
Ithaca, Cornell University Press.
·
Eisenberg, Avigail,
and Jeff Spinner-Halev, ed. 2005. Minorities within
Minorities: Equality, Rights, and Diversity. Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press.
·
Elliott, Carl.
2003a. “Does Your Patient Have A Beetle in His Box? Language
Games and Psychopathology,” in the Grammar of Politics:
Wittgenstein and Political Philosophy, Cressida J.
Heyes (Ed.). Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
·
–––. 2003b.
“Amputees by Choice”. In Better Than Well: American
Medicine Meets the American Dream. New York: Norton.
·
Fanon, Frantz.
Trans. Charles Markmann. 1968. Black Skin, White Masks.
New York: Grove Press.
·
Farred, Grant. 2000.
“Endgame Identity? Mapping the New Left Roots of Identity
Politics.” New Literary History 31:4: 627-48.
·
Firestone,
Shulamith. 1970. The Dialectic of Sex: The Case for
Feminist Revolution. New York: Morrow.
·
Foster, Lawrence and
Patricia Herzog (Eds). 1994. Defending Diversity:
Contemporary Philosophical Perspectives on Pluralism and
Multiculturalism. Amherst, MA: University of
Massachusetts Press.
·
Foucault, Michel.
1980. The History of Sexuality. New York: Vintage.
·
Fraser, Nancy. 1997.
Justice Interruptus: Critical Reflections on the
“Post-Socialist” Condition. New York. Routledge.
·
Friedan, Betty.
1963. The Feminine Mystique. New York: Norton.
·
Frye, Marilyn. 1983.
The Politics of Reality: Essays in Feminist Theory.
Trumansberg, NY: The Crossing Press.
·
Garber, Marjorie.
1995. Vice Versa: Bisexuality and the Eroticism of
Everyday Life. New York: Routledge.
·
Gilligan, Carol.
1993 (1982). In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory
and Women's Development. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press.
·
Gutmann, Amy (Ed.).
1994. Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of
Recognition. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
·
Hacking, Ian. 1999
The Social Construction of What? Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
·
Hartsock, Nancy C.
M. 1998. The Feminist Standpoint Revisited and Other
Essays. Boulder: Westview.
·
Haslanger, Sally.
1995 “Ontology and Social Construction.” Philosophical
Topics 23.
·
–––. 2005. “Social
Construction: Who? What? Where? How?” In Theorizing
Feminisms ed. Elizabeth Hackett and Sally Haslanger.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
·
Heyes, Cressida J.
2000. Line Drawings: Defining Women through Feminist
Practice. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
·
–––. Forthcoming.
“Feminist Solidarity after Queer Theory: The Case of
Transgender.” Signs 28:2.
·
Hooks, Bell. 1981.
Ain't I a Woman? Black Women and Feminism. Boston:
South End Press.
·
Ignatiev, Noel.
1995. How the Irish Became White. New York:
Routledge.
·
Irigaray, Luce,
trans. Catherine Porter. 1985. This Sex Which is Not One.
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
·
Kruks, Sonia. 2000.
Retrieving Experience: Subjectivity and Recognition in
Feminist Politics. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University
Press.
·
Kymlicka, Will
(Ed.). 1995. The Rights of Minority Cultures.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
·
Laden, Anthony.
2001. Reasonably Radical: Deliberative Liberalism and
the Politics of Identity. Ithaca: Cornell University
Press.
·
Laden, Anthony and
David Owen ed. 2007. Multiculturalism and Political
Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
·
Lott, Eric. 2000.
“After Identity, Politics: The Return of Universalism.”
New Literary History 31:4: 665-80.
·
Lugones, María.
1994. “Purity, Impurity, and Separation.” Signs 19:
458-79.
·
McIntosh, Mary.
1968. “The Homosexual Role.” Social Problems 16:2.
·
McIntosh, Peggy.
1993. “White Privilege and Male Privilege: A Personal
Account of Coming to See Correspondences Through Work in
Women's Studies,” in Gender Basics: Feminist
Perspectives on Women and Men, Anne Minas (Ed.).
Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.
·
Martin, Jane Roland.
1994. “Methodological Essentialism, False Difference, and
Other Dangerous Traps.” Signs 19: 630-57.
·
Mills, Charles.
1997. The Racial Contract. Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press.
·
Mohanty, Chandra
Talpade. 1988. “Under Western Eyes: Feminist Scholarship and
Colonial Discourse,” in Third World Women and the
Politics of Feminism, Chandra Talpade Mohanty, Ann
Russo, and Lourdes Torres (Eds.). Bloomington: Indiana
University Press, 1991.
·
Moi, Toril. 2000.
What is a Woman? And Other Essays. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
·
Nelson, Hilde
Lindemann. 2001. Damaged Identities, Narrative Repair.
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
·
Okin, Susan Moller,
et al. 1999. Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women?
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
·
Omi, Michael and
Howard Winant. 1994 (1986). Racial Formation in the
United States: From the 1960s to the 1990s. New York:
Routledge.
·
Pateman, Carole.
1988. The Sexual Contract. Cambridge: Polity.
·
Phelan, Shane. 1994.
Getting Specific: Postmodern Lesbian Politics.
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
·
–––. 1989.
Identity Politics: Lesbian Feminism and the Limits of
Community. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
·
Phillips, Anne.
2007. Multiculturalism without Culture. Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
·
Piper, Adrian. 1996.
“Passing for Black, Passing for White,” in Passing and
the Fictions of Identity, Elaine K. Ginsberg (Ed.).
Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
·
Radicalesbians. 1988
(first published 1975). “The Woman Identified Woman,” in
For Lesbians Only: A Separatist Anthology, Sarah
Hoagland and Julia Penelope (Eds.). London: Onlywomen Press.
·
Rawls, John. 1971.
A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
·
Rich, Adrienne.
1980. “Compulsory Heterosexuality and Lesbian Existence.”
Signs 5:4.
·
Rose, Nikolas. 1997.
“Assembling the MOdern Self.”. In Rewriting the Self:
Histories from the Renaissance to the Present ed. Roy
Porter. London: Routledge.
·
Ruddick, Sara. 1989.
Maternal Thinking: Toward a Politics of Peace. New
York: Ballantine.
·
Sandilands,
Catriona. 1995. “From Natural Identity to Radical
Democracy.” Environmental Ethics 17: 75-91.
·
Scott, Joan. 1992.
“Experience,” in Feminists Theorize the Political,
Judith Butler and Joan W. Scott (Eds.). New York: Routledge.
·
Sedgwick, Eve
Kosofsky. 1990. Epistemology of the Closet.
Berkeley: University of California Press.
·
Silvers, Anita.
1998. “Formal Justice.” In Disability, Difference,
Discrimination: Perspectives on Justice in Bioethics and
Public Policy. Anita Silvers, David Wasserman, and Mary
B. Mahowald. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
·
Spelman, Elizabeth
V. 1988. Inessential Woman: Problems of Exclusion in
Feminist Thought. Boston: Beacon.
·
Spivak, Gayatri, ed.
Sara Harasym. 1990. The Post-Colonial Critic:
Interviews, Strategies, and Dialogues. New York:
Routledge.
·
Taylor, Charles.
1989. Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern
Identity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
·
Terry, Jennifer.
1999. An American Obsession: Science, Medicine, and
Homosexuality in Modern Society. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
·
Turkle, Sherry.
1995. Life on the Screen: Identity in the Age of the
Internet. New York: Simon and Schuster.
·
Wald, Priscilla.
2000. “Future Perfect: Grammar, Genes, and Geography.”
New Literary History 31:4: 681-708.
·
Wendell, Susan.
1996. The Rejected Body: Feminist Philosophical
Reflections on Disability. New York: Routledge.
·
Williams, Melissa.
1998. Voice, Trust, and Memory: Marginalized Groups and
the Failings of Liberal Representation. Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
·
Williams, Patricia.
1991. The Alchemy of Race and Rights. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
·
Young, Iris Marion.
1990. Justice and the Politics of Difference.
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
·
–––. 1997.
Intersecting Voices: Dilemmas of Gender, Political
Philosophy and Policy. Princeton: Princeton University
Press.
·
–––. 2000.
Inclusion and Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.